Harel Barzilai for Spring 1997 Educ. class by Prof. Avery Solomon
David Henderson's short paper, Proof as a Convincing Argument That
Answers -- Why? addresses two key issues. The first concerns what
constitutes a "proof", and in particular, what makes a proof
convincing. The second issue concerns how human beings
communicate with each other about mathematics.
These are related by the opening quote by the Dalai Lama: it is our
deepest personal meanings, coming from our deepest personal
experiences, which determine whether a proof is satisfying to us;
these inner experiences and meaning, in turn, can be a source of
differing mathematical viewpoints between people, and conversely, a
source of a rich diversity of mathematical viewpoints, to the extent
we learn to communicate, and most of all, listen across our
different experiences.
In a way, Henderson is radically defining the notion of "proof" --
"Proof as a Convincing Argument That Answers -- Why?" takes proof
beyond "Showing that a proposition P is true" to "Showing us
convincingly why P is true".
To the extent that Henderson does not mean to suggest that the former,
more limited type of proof is without any value, I agree with his
emphasis on the latter, deeper definition of proof. Indeed we can draw
some conclusions which Henderson does not (explicitly) draw in this
paper.
He writes that: "...you have probably had the experience of reading a
proof and following each step logically but still not being satisfied
because the proof did not lead you to experience the answer to your
why-question" and goes on to say "In fact most proofs in the
literature are not written out in such a [logical step-by-step] way
... [and] even if they were so written, most proofs would be too long
and complicated.. for a person to check each step".
But another statement about "most proofs in the literature" is
omitted, despite having just spoken about why-questions: Most proofs
in the literature do not answer it, and do not, in general, even
try to answer the why-question, and furthermore, there is a
cultural attitude in mathematics that that would not be the path of
greatest "efficiency", or would even be a waste of time.
Why prove 10 theorems with very clear, satisfying explanations,
background, and motivation, with a full, clear exposition, when your
career would be hurt by this, relative your having proved 20 (or even
11) theorems in the narrow, unsatisfying sense?
One cannot make a sensible (or even rational) attempt to analyze the
state of the mathematical culture without looking at the cost/benefit,
or perhaps better, punishment/reward system under which most
mathematicians live -- Thurson's "Theorems-credit"
If the system credits you with $1 for each theorem proved, and $1
additionally for each theorem (your own or someone else's) made very
clear, expanded, answering why-questions, etc, we would see a very
different mathematical literature. A system which gives a $1 credit
for the former, and anywhere from a nickel, to a negative amount for
the latter, on the other hand, would produce results very similar to
what we see in today's literature.
Such a cost/benefit analysis would explain the (otherwise)
"irrational" allocation of human hours: what could have taken the
author of a proof an additional, say, 3 hours to explain more clearly,
is saved (savings = 3), while the authors (say) N readers must
therefore struggle, each, an extra 1 (or 3 or 10) hours more, than
they would otherwise have had to do, to decipher the proof -- at a
total human cost of N readers (say 100) times, say 2 hours extra each,
of 200-3=197 more human-hours wasted as a result.
Under today's mathematical political climate, I would be inviting upon
myself explanations such as "well, you're just dumb" were I not to
cite a Respectable mathematician, so I will: it is while observing my
advisor, who has been called by at least one source the strongest
topologist at Cornell, that I noticed that I am not the only one who
find themselves struggling for way longer than it would have otherwise
been necessary, trying to decipher a proof which, it becomes clearer
and clearer over time, would have taken far, far less time to decipher
were a better job done in exposition, motivation, and other efforts
towards conveying an intimate understanding expended, the kind of
expenditure that the current cost/benefit reward system in our
mathematical culture does not promote, and in fact the opposite.
At the same time, I feel that neither Henderson nor we, should, by
omission, unintentionally suggest that there is no interest
whatsoever in why the commutative law follows from Peano's
axioms. Such additions to that proof as, an exposition of the
motivations for mathematician's seeking, in the first place, such an
axiom system, would go a long way towards answering important
why-questions, leaving it for each reader to decide how much of the
"dry" part of the proof they need, at present, to read and understand,
given their present mathematical interests and motivations for reading
the paper in question.
These comments about Henderson's paper would not be complete
without noting that his "multiculturalism" argument is a powerful
one. It also implies that women need to listen to men more closely,
but I don't think that makes it less feminist. It also implies that
blacks need to listen to whites more closely, but I don't think that
makes it less powerfully a statement against a "prejudicial ear"
(mathematical or even otherwise) towards ethnic minorities. It does, I
think present a strong case, based on facts, experience, and
well-argued reasoning, which does not replace, but supplements well
the other important arguments -- based on non-racist non-sexist
assumptions about human beings, basic decency, and so forth -- for a
"multicultural mathematical culture"
Just as Henderson's paper started with a quote,
we would like to conclude by quoting another important figure, on what
might today be called a multicultural theme:
"The tragedy of such a fate lies not merely in the unfair treatment
to which these minorities are automatically subjected in social and
economic matters, but also in the fact that under the suggestive
influence of the majorities most of the victims themselves
succumb to the same prejudice and regard their brethren as
inferior beings.
"This second and greater part of the evil can be overcome by
closer combination and by deliberate education of the minority, whose
spiritual liberation can thus be accomplished. The deliberate efforts
of the American negroes in this direction deserve approval and
assistance."
--Albert Einstein (From: The World As I See It, 1934.)
"It seems to be a universal fact that minorities --
especially when the individuals composing them are distinguished by
physical peculiarities -- are treated by the majorities among whom the
live as an inferior order of being.